Why the backers of assisted dying keep coming back

Filed in Ethics by on June 11, 2014 3 Comments

falk

Lord Falconer’s Assisted Dying Bill had its First Reading in the House of Lords last week, and its second is expected on or close to 18 July. The Bill aims to change the law in order “to enable competent adults who are terminally ill to be provided at their request with specified assistance to end their own life.” It is the fourth attempt to legalise assisted suicide in Britain in the past decade; in 2006, 2009 and 2010, similar bills were rejected by Parliament – mostly on grounds of  public safety rather than ethics.

This Falconer Bill is no less flawed than its predecessors. If passed, it would endanger vulnerable individuals with terminal illness, erode their right to good medical care, and undermine the ethos of the medical profession.

The existing law

The 1961 Suicide Act carries penalties of up to 14 years’ imprisonment for assisting in a suicide. The Commission on Assisted Dying, the body (chaired by Lord Falconer, and funded by the novelist Terry Pratchett) behind the Bill, claims that current law is “inadequate, incoherent and should not continue”. Yet the law has been under scrutiny many times and has undergone many modifications; the Crown Prosecution Service is very clear on which factors are relevant for prosecution in cases of assisting suicide for a chronically or terminally ill individual.

After the 2009 Debbie Purdy case, in which a woman with primary progressive multiple sclerosis sought clarification on how the Suicide Act would be enforced if her husband helped her to take her own life, the Director of Public Prosecutions (DPP) issued guidelines on when, and when not, to prosecute such cases.

It laid out six factors that would mitigate against a decision to prosecute, including “a voluntary, clear, settled and informed decision” on the part of the victim, and evidence that the suspect had been “wholly motivated by compassion”.

But if the suspect is a doctor or nurse, their professional status will be treated as an aggravating factor. This is in line with the 2010 submission made by the Royal College of Physicians to the DPP, which stated that: “Our duty of care is to work with patients to mitigate and overcome their clinical difficulties and suffering… The trust afforded doctors and nurses in particular gives their views considerable weight with their patients and the public. Clinicians’ duties of care entail active pursuit of alternative solutions to assisted suicide, not its facilitation.”

The law retains a firm prohibition against encouraging and assisting someone to commit suicide, while still providing for discretion on the part of prosecutors in individual cases. In doing so, it provides vulnerable people a strong protection from exploitation and harm, while sensibly acknowledging that the rare cases in which the law is flouted solely out of compassion pose no threat to public safety.

Indeed, no British citizen who has helped a relative travel to the Dignitas clinic has ever been prosecuted. As Lord Alex Carlile QC puts it, it is “a hard law, with a kind face”. The desire to change it, in other words, cannot spring from a realistic fear that a kindly relative who helps a suffering person to die would ever face prosecution from the law.

Who supports the Bill?

Lord Falconer’s Commission on Assisted Dying includes advocates of assisted suicide from various fields. It was set up after two independent Parliamentary Select Committees examined the issue and concluded that the law should not be changed. In 2012, the Commission published evidence which claimed there was, in fact, a strong case for an assisted suicide law.

The Commission’s call for evidence submissions was boycotted by around 40 leading medical, ethical, and disability rights organisations due to bias in the Commission’s remit and composition. These included the Association for Palliative Medicine, the Royal Society of Medicine, the Equalities and Human Rights Commission, the Royal Colleges of Nursing, Physicians and Psychiatrists and the British Medical Association, which in June 2011 overwhelmingly passed a motion disputing the Commission’s claim to impartiality and independence. They rightly saw it as a lobby that was seeking to introduce euthanasia by stealth.

The medical professionals on the Commission’s panel are outliers. This agreed positions of the main doctors’ bodies are all firmly against. The Association of Palliative Medicine says it is morally and clinically unacceptable for a doctor to assist a person in committing suicide; the Royal College of GPs says that, as of February 2014, 77 per cent of its members oppose the legalization of assisted dying; while the British Medical Association opposes all forms of assisted dying and “supports the current legal framework, which allows compassionate and ethical care for the dying”.

In advocating a change in the law, the Commission ignores the judgement of two independent Parliamentary scrutiny committees and the opinion of the medical profession, who have well-founded concerns about the ramifications this law would have for public safety and clinical practice.

Inadequate Safeguards

The moral issue of assisted suicide cannot be ignored. We need to expose the fallacy of the premise that life loses value the closer it is to death, or the radically individualist idea that “dignity in dying” requires the exercise of control over the time and manner of our death. True dignity lies in recognizing our need of help, and receiving it – comfort, pain relief, security, peace, and so on. That has implications for what kind of a society we want to be. We need a debate about dying, about what kind of changes we need in order to guarantee compassion and respect, as well as palliative and other kinds of care.

But the debate about changing the law in this instance inevitably centers on the public safety issue — the effect on society of changing the law, above all on vulnerable people. The reason why previous attempts such as the 2006 Assisted Dying for the Terminally Ill Bill have not passed is because Parliament concluded they would undermine the legal protections due to vulnerable members of society. The Falconer Bill is no different.

The Bill states that in order to be eligible for assisted suicide, a person must have a prognosis of six months or less to live, a “clear and settled intent” to end their life and the mental capacity to make such a decision. But it does not offer any guidelines on how to assess whether or not these eligibility criteria have been met, claiming instead that guidelines will be included in codes of practice drawn up after the law has been approved.

A report analysing the Falconer Bill’s safeguards, compiled by a group of peers with expertise in the fields of medicine and disability rights for the research organisation Living and Dying Well, judged this to be “woefully inadequate” from a public safety perspective.

“It is not unusual for detailed protocols and procedures of legislation to be left to subsequent codes of practice,” they write. “But mental capacity, clear and settled intent and freedom of coercion are not details but fundamentals – critical and integral aspects of any proposal to license doctors to end lives.”

More recently Baroness Hollins, Emeritus Professor of Psychiatry of Disability at St George’s University of London (and coincidentally a member of Pope Francis’s new commission on sexual abuse) has written about the difficulties of assessing mental capacity and the high cost of error.

When doctors assess capacity, they do it to protect their patient from harm, not to clear the way for them to commit suicide. If they make a mistake, the mistake is on the side of patient protection. Licensing doctors to supply lethal drugs to some of their patients would be an extremely worrying development because, if you look at what has happened in the small number of other countries that have legalised assisted suicide, there have been mistakes.

The fact that the Bill does not stipulate referral for psychiatric assessment in order to rule out judgement-impairing mental conditions is particularly concerning in light of evidence from the US state of Oregon, where assisted suicide was legalised in 1998: a 2008 British Medical Journal paper concluded that Oregon’s assisted dying law “may not be adequately protecting mentally ill patients” after it found evidence that cases of clinical depression and anxiety had gone undiagnosed by assessing doctors.

Every law has its flaws, of course, and is susceptible to misapplication. But with assisted dying laws, misapplication costs lives. The Falconer Bill’s safeguards are a poor attempt to remove elements of risk from a legal innovation that is inherently risky, one that is open to manipulation and fails to protect vulnerable individuals.

Effect on Medicine

Allowing doctors to end patients’ lives in certain circumstances, thus undermining their right to life and to best medical care, would represent a major change not only to the criminal law but also to clinical practice. That’s why associations of doctors and other health professionals oppose a change in the law: it is impossible to rule out coercion; and any law that puts the doctor in a position of being asked to help kill their patient would have a chilling effect on doctor-patient relationships.

This is the main reason why the Royal College of GPs says the majority of its members oppose a change in the law. GPs know that, in practice, they are the ones who would be asked to enable their patients to kill themselves, and it is not a burden they believe should be placed on a profession whose task is to heal not harm. People wanting to end their lives would find few GPs who had no ethical objections to assisting them in taking their lives, and who also had sufficient knowledge of the patients involved to know if they met the Bill’s criteria.

This has been a problem in Oregon, where the median length of the doctor-patient relationship for those who died through assisted suicide between 1998 and 2009 was ten weeks, and in many cases was no more than two or three weeks. How can a knowledgeable assessment of a patient’s mental state and intention – one that can rule out impairments to the patient’s judgement or evidence of coercion – be made in such a short time?

The Bill’s requirement that the individual seeking assisted suicide must have a terminal prognosis of six months or less also assumes that this, too, is an exact science. Yet expert medical evidence given to Parliament in recent years shows that guessing how long someone has to live is extremely unreliable.

Reliable prognoses tend to be those made within a time-frame of days or hours, not weeks or months. Evidence heard by the Select Committee examining the 2006 Assisted Dying for the Terminally Ill Bill proposed by Lord Joffe made clear the difficulty of making the kind of prognoses required for licensing an assisted suicide. The Royal College of GPs, for example, told the committee that when estimates are being made for people living for a matter of months “the scope for error can extend into years.” The Bill’s requirement for accurate medium-term prognosis is clinically unworkable, and would certainly lead to individuals seeking to end their lives on the basis of inaccurate information.

A matter of choice?

Supporters of assisted suicide, whether high-profile figures or ordinary members of the public, advance their case on grounds of personal choice and autonomy. They say people who have a good reason for ending their lives should have the freedom to do so, and that the exercise of this freedom is what gives them dignity in dying.

Yet the Bill does not attempt to provide for assisted death for all of the small minority of terminally and chronically ill people who request it, for it recognises how dangerous this would be. Instead, it makes an attempt, through its widely-criticised safeguards, to prescribe which terminally ill individuals will and will not be considered for assisted death.

The Bill’s mental capacity and self-administration criteria would rule out, for instance, the late Tony Nicklinson or the novelist campaigner Sir Terry Pratchett, well-known advocates of assisted death. For Mr Nicklinson, to have his life ended would have required alterations not to the law on suicide, but to the law on murder, while the need for a terminal prognosis would rule out those, like Debbie Purdy, with chronic but not fatal conditions such as multiple sclerosis.

This Bill would offer no extra legal assistance to large numbers of the small minority of chronically or terminally ill individuals who are determined to end their own lives, whose relatives are already offered protection from prosecution by existing DPP guidelines.

But it would change the law in a way that endangers vulnerable individuals who need the support, care and encouragement necessary to live fulfilling and dignified lives with terminal illness.

Baroness Campbell, former head of the Equality and Human Rights Commission, wrote last year that, “The existing law on assisted suicide rests on a natural frontier. It rests on the principle that we do not involve ourselves in deliberately bringing about the deaths of other people. What the proponents of ‘assisted dying’ want is to replace that clear and bright line with an arbitrary and permeable one.” Recently, she said Falconer’s proposals sent a shiver down her spine.

Falconer’s purpose

Why does Lord Falconer keep returning to Parliament with a Bill that would change the law for a very few? Because if it became law it would cross the line signaled by Baroness Cambpell: it would secure the state’s backing for the concept that it is in some people’s best interests to die. No longer would there be a  healthcare system committed to recognising the value and dignity of every individual right up until the end of their life. Belgium, which recently approved the euthanasia of children, is what lies down the road. The logic of assisted suicide leads inexorably in that direction.

The debate over assisted dying is not a debate abut compassion versus cruelty, or choice versus coercion. It’s a debate over whether the law should consider each individual as equally deserving of life, and whether those who are terminally ill should expect the same rights and protections under the law as everybody else. Falconer’s bill torpedoes that principle, and must continue to be resisted.

[Megan Hodder]

Tags: , , ,

Catholic Voices

About the Author ()

These articles from Catholic Voices are re-posted here, with permission, from the Catholic Voices Comment website at http://cvcomment.org/

Comments (3)

Trackback URL | Comments RSS Feed

  1. John O'Neill says:

    The Church teaches that life is sacred irrespective of the ‘quality’ of life that individuals possess. If we make exceptions and erode this teaching we will open ourselves to condemning every type of anthropomorphic imperfection. The British Government would do better by promoting the Hospice movement and the possibility of death with dignity.

  2. shieldsheafson says:

    We are full of contradictions.

    Who would have thought that the ‘human rights’ project could become so powerful that it risked being turned against itself, and against the human person?

    Basic human rights are not created by governments; they are pre-political. Human rights arise from a natural order whose laws can be discovered through study and experience. To remove human rights from that context could destroy their universality.

    With cultural relativism, we risk the denial of universality in the name of different cultural, political, social and even religious outlooks. The use of this cultural specificity, e.g., homosexuality, abortion, may indeed mask violations of human rights.

    Some of the world’s worst human rights violators have attempted to hide behind this type of argument.

    We have fallen into the trap that characterizes the mindset of the arbitrarily appointed professional culture of many lawyers, civil servants, and NGOs – a kind of – ism that is insensitive to local particularities and that insists on its own dogmatic interpretations of human rights.

    Relativism has penetrated so deeply into popular culture that good men and women are increasingly unable to say why any values should be defended, or why any conduct should be condemned, except that it is a matter of preference. But if there are no common truths to which people of different backgrounds and cultures can appeal, it is difficult to see how universal human rights can be upheld.

    How can juridical norms be found that guarantee freedom, human dignity and human rights? In anticipating the standard response referring to democratic processes of deliberation, one observes that public argumentation in contemporary democracies aims above all at attaining majorities, and that sensitivity to the truth is constantly overruled by sensitivity to interests; often special interests that do not truly serve everyone.

    These ‘equality’ laws protect pregnant women, but only if we accept that every woman has the right to kill her baby. These ‘equality’ laws will protect the aged, unless they are dispensed through euthanasia. The disabled will be protected from harm, provided they happen to escape abortion or infanticide.

    Marriage will be protected, but at the expense of defining marriage to include even the most casual and temporary union of anyone with anyone. Your religion will be protected, as long as you don’t believe that it actually determines what people should really believe and how they should act.

    In every case the result will not be equality, but the iron-fisted imposition of a radical secular agenda. The aged, infirm, disabled will be at risk; secularism will be the sole established religion; and marriage will soon disappear into mist.

    And where will the ‘equality’ or ‘human rights’ be then?

  3. Paul Rodden says:

    To be realistic, Catholicism in England is not exactly offering any noticeable and tangible alternative ‘lifestyle’ of human flourishing to counter their ‘deathstyle’, is it?

    The simple reason ‘they’ come back is the same reason Nazism, etc., comes back.

    Like nature, society abhors a vacuum, and totalitarianisms fit the bill nicely. It attracts people who differ from people in asylums who claim to be Jesus, only by not adverting to the fact they think they are, and so believe they have divine power over life and death, and are discovered only when it’s too late.

    That said, even though many ‘doctors’ are against assisted dying, isn’t it more likely to be based on evidence too, so underneath, their decisions are based on factors as relative as those for assisted dying?

    So, although one looks ‘positive’ and on ‘our side’, and the other not, in reality, they’re both ‘against’ us as they are both likely to be functioning from an identical frame of reference: that truth – the value and dignity of human life in this instance – is inductive, and therefore conditional. They simply disagree on the data (inductive), and therefore the value of the person (which for them is not substantive in its own right, but completely conditional upon the former, in their worldview).

    ‘Ethics’, as outlined so well by shieldsheafson’s comment, above, illustrates the point so well, for it has replaced Virtue. ‘Ethics’ is the product of Epistemology, whilst Virtue is the domain of Metaphysics, and that difference really matters. (See Karol Wojtyla, The Acting Person, and Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue, for example).

    Virtue guarantees so much more than ‘Ethics’. ‘Ethics’ has no grip on a slippery slope as it has no real intentionality or traction, unlike Virtue, where the person has to go against their nature (their climb to excellence arete) to comply with any form of slippery-slope anti-humanism. In short, the Virtuous person has to sell out on their very nature, unlike the ‘Ethical person who just sees it as a ‘bad call’. The thinking about persons by virtuous people is ‘joined up’ as they say.

    Virtue not only guarantees the sanctity of life, but also how people are treated if allowed to live in general: the quality of the tenderness and palliative care they will receive, too. It’s focus is broad.

    However, ‘Ethics’ will not, and cannot, guarantee any of these. Hence the unending reports of school, priest, care home abuse of all forms. This abuse will reduce only in proportion to the draconian severity of deterrents – in each domain – if not a matter of character, and that’s exactly what we see happening.

    With ‘Ethics’, the State ‘solves’ one problem by obsessively policing it with all their resources (e.g., ‘Operation Yew Tree’), so vice and abuse just grow everywhere they’ve taken away the deterrent (resources) to police the latest Moral Panic, until the next one… (See the excellent and insightful work of Phillip Jenkins on Moral Panics and Paedophile Priests.)

    In other words, our paradigms are so far apart, we might as well be talking Chinese to secular culture. For the Virtuous (Catholic) paradigm, the drivers are internal, for the Ethical (Secular) paradigm, the drivers are external. The first is teleological in a transcendent sense (Common Good), the second, in an instrumental sense (beneficial to me) in compliance with the law, casuistic lawyers to find loop-holes for me, or simply trying not to get caught.

    We can bleat, or we can look in the mirror, for we can’t stop them because Catholicism in England on the shop floor (and even among most of the clergy) is, de facto, squabbling factions, no different from Protestant congregationalism at best, secular relativism at its worst, whatever we might fantasise about what it is, de jure. It is driven predominantly by how everything relates ‘to me’, even in the TLM crowd.

    Our Bishops and priests have encouraged us to toboggan down the relativist/subjectivist slope for fifty years. Now we’re at the bottom of the slope and we have to start to climb. Like any mountaineering, the journey will be perilous and we might be killed, but exhilarating nonetheless.

    Some talk about a ‘feminised Church’. Have they read Mulieris Dignitatem? It’s an insult.

    Rather, we have imported an obese, corn-syrup and burger-stuffed, 1045-Channel TV, type of Catholicism from well-meaning but ill-conceived notions of ‘ecumenism’.

    We simply have no argument, no place to stand – unless we don’t mind sounding like the most risible hypocrites – until we get in shape. At that stage we will be building and funding hospices offering great palliative care to show what our mission is.

    At the moment, all the secular knows about us is the tripe they hear from Dan Brown (fiction taken as truth), and from the media about the Magdalene Laundries, and the Bon Secours sisters in Tuam…
    http://www.aleteia.org/en/society/article/scapegoating-the-sisters-for-the-deaths-of-800-babies-5875079674068992

Leave a Reply to shieldsheafson Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *